Companies, we are always being told, ought to behave
ethically. What does that mean? We all have a rough idea of what constitutes
ethical conduct in people. But a company is an abstraction. What ethical
obligations does it have, and how do we know if it is fulfilling them?
This is not as impractical a question as it sounds.
Corporate ethics is bedevilled by lack of definitions. The less we know
what we mean, the more likely we are to be disappointed in our expectations.
There is a direct analogy here with the law. It
is an established principle that a company is legally a separate entity
from those who work for it or own it. So how do you hold a company liable
for criminal acts?
In the UK, the answer has been that officers responsible
for the company can be held to be its "controlling mind". If
they act criminally in carrying out their duties, the company is criminally
liable.
This is something of a dodge, and has proved tricky
to enforce. There have, for instance, been attempts to charge companies
with corporate manslaughter, after rail accidents and the like. All have
failed save one, the case of a one-man leisure company responsible for
a boating accident.
In other cases, it proved too complex to establish
which people made up the controlling mind, and whether they themselves
had acted criminally. The UK government is now considering a new offence
of "corporate killing". Good luck to it.
As for the broader field of ethics, it helps to
consider what the purpose of a company is in the first place. One school
of thought, associated with Friedrich Hayek and Milton Friedman, says
its sole purpose is to make a profit. That may sound bleak, but there
is logic to it. Big companies are potentially very powerful. The more
responsibilities we charge them with, the more power we risk giving them.
It sounds brutal, for instance, to say that the
job of an army is to kill people as directed by the government. But the
more you give the army other duties - upholding the law, for instance
- the more risk you run of military dictatorship.
So far, so logical. But the Friedman view is not
universally accepted. For a start, is it really the case that companies
do nothing but maximise their profits?
Given the advance of investor capitalism in recent
years, it is probably more true than it used to be. But it is equally
plain that companies sometimes act on other motives: self-preservation,
for instance, or self-aggrandisement.
As for the argument that companies are abstract
entities, there is room for common sense. Norman Bowie, recently appointed
professor of business ethics at the London Business School, puts it this
way.
Suppose, he says, you receive a bill for oil from
BP Amoco. The bill does not say it comes from the chief executive, but
from the company. You pay it just the same.
"We speak in terms of corporate entities doing
things all the time," Professor Bowie says. "By analogy, we
can talk of a company being ethical."
In addition, common sense tells us that some companies
do in fact behave ethically over decades, despite the fact that senior
management have changed completely over the period. Other companies have
a persistent tendency to transgress, for example by offering bribes.
Granted all that, what kinds of ethical behaviour
can we legitimately expect from companies? Begin with ethical obligations
as applied to people. These, Prof Bowie argues, fall under two broad headings.
The first is contractual. If you promise to pay
me $50, you are ethically obliged to keep that promise.
The second is natural. If you see a toddler struggling
in 2ft of water, and all it costs you to rescue it is wet shoes, almost
everyone would argue you have a natural obligation to save it. If you
pour petrol over a cat and set it alight, almost everyone would agree
you are being cruel.
It is easy to think of companies observing contractual
obligations. They enter contractual arrangements every day, not all of
them legally enforceable. As the motto of the old London Stock Exchange
had it, verbum meum pactum - my word is my bond. In commerce, trust is
a valuable commodity.
What about natural obligations? It is much harder,
as Prof Bowie concedes, to apply those to companies.
"But suppose a company lays people off just
before Christmas, or just before they are entitled to a pension,"
he says. "Wouldn't it make sense to say that corporation is cruel?
Some companies do act in that way, and beyond a certain point we can say
that certain companies are crueller than others." Even if we grant
all that, our difficulties are not over. If a person acts unethically
- as opposed to illegally - society has plenty of sanctions, such as ostracism
or public shaming.
Similarly, society can vent its disapproval of
an unethical company by boycotting its goods or services. But whereas
a person can suffer emotionally, the only damage that can be inflicted
on a company is financial. This affects not the managers, who were guilty
of the misconduct, but the shareholders, who were not.
This brings us back to the parallel with criminal
justice. Let us grant that we are entitled to expect certain kinds of
conduct from companies. If we are not to be disappointed, we must accept
it is by no means clear how to hold them to it. [email protected] Copyright
Financial Times Limited 1999. All Rights Reserved.
FTviaNewsEDGE
Copyright (c) 1999 Financial Times Limited Received via NewsEDGE
from NewsEdge Corporation: 08/11/99 21:10:07
|